Set Theory: Functions
What are functions in set theory? “Consider the function f(x)
= x3, i.e., f assigns to each real number
its cube.” “Let g assign to each country in the
world its capital city.” (Lipschutz, 1998, pp. 94-116). These
are examples. There are three basic features of functions.
The first feature is that one element, ai, of
the set A is assigned to, aligned with one unique element,
bi, of the set B. This is one-to-one,
is injective – as when one value of x is matched with
one value of x3; ai = x
= 3 is matched with bi = f(x) = x3
= 27. For the countries, g (France) = Paris, g (Denmark)
= Copenhagen.
The second feature is that every element bi of
B is to be aligned with some element ai
of A. This is not one-to-one; this is onto, surjective. Examples
illustrate this feature. Thus f(x) = x2
yields for ai = -x = -2 and ai
= x = 2 the same number, bi = 4. For
the countries, g (England) and g (Scotland) = London.
There is convergence on 4 and on London.
The third feature is that when a function is both one-to-one and onto,
like f(x) = x3 and g (France)
= Paris the function is a one-to-one correspondence, is bijective.
If a function is a one-to-one correspondence, then it is invertible
(reversible): f: A B
and f-1: B A,
wherein all elements of the sets A and B are considered.
The application of functions to adaptation takes two forms. The first
is the narrow form: the function of adaptedness assigns to each entity
an environmental aspect – or the function of adaptedness binds
each entity, each particular, to a facet of the environment, another
particular. In spite of the order difference, the basic structure
requirement is evident: one entity, a biological particular, is separated
from its essential property of adaptedness, which is separated from
an environmental particular.
Conifers and the Third Principle of Adaptation
The third principle of adaptation is (nominalistically) that if entity
x is adapted to a second entity y, then the second
is adapted to the first – and to be logically valid, if the
second, y, is adapted to the first, x, then the
first is adapted to the second (so the two are adapted to each other).
Now the issue is two-fold. Data will be presented to uphold the third
principle. And the presentation will be recast into the mold of functions.
In Figure 1 are presented three non-overlapping species of coastally
restricted forests of North America (Laderman 1998). In the coastal
belt between southern Alaska and Washington state there is the Alaska
yellow-cedar (Charmaecyparis nootkatensis). Though abundant
and in places occurring in pure stands, it has declined. This decline
started 100 years ago but is slight now. South of this species the
coast redwood (Sequoia sempervirens) is abundant in the fog-shrouded
coastal region from Oregon well into California. In spite of logging
its regrowth shows it to be well suited to its present locale. Before
the Pleistocene glaciation it was widespread in the West (Axelrod,
1976). Though it failed to regain its widespread distribution after
the ice melted, still it seems well established in its present locale.
The distribution of the Atlantic white cedar (Chamaecyparis thyoides)
is intermittent along the East coast and Gulf coast. But it is a successful
species, its net growth amply exceeding loss due to logging.
These non-overlapping species are adapted to their locales which are
adapted to them (third principle, nominalistically).
These three species and three locales make up two sets of entities,
of particulars. Species and locale are bound together by being adapted
to each other. As previously mentioned there are two ways to express
this binding: the function of adaptedness assigns to each species
its locale; the function of adaptedness binds each species to its
locale. In Figure 1 the three species are a1, a2,
a3 and the three locales are b1, b2,
b3. The function of adaptedness binds a1
to b1, a2 to b2,
a3 to b3 – i.e., f(a1)
= b1, f(a2) = b2,
f(a3) = b3. This
is one-to-one and onto; so this is a one-to-one correspondence, is
bijective. But the locales seem well delimited in a unique, non-overlapping,
idiosyncratic manner to their species and support their species quite
well. Thus the function of adaptedness is invertible; the function
is reversible. This means that the function of adaptedness is a one-to-one
correspondence both ways.
In Figure 1 are shown the vast and almost identical distributions
of the white spruce (Picea glauca) and the black spruce (Picea
mariana) (Brockman and Merrilees, 2001). Here there is a set
of two species and a set of just one locale. This is not one-to-one;
this is onto, surjective – because for every element of B
(there is only one) there is aligned some element of A (the
two species). The elements of A converge, because f(a1)
= b1 and f(a2) =
b1 but a1 a2.
So the function of adaptedness does not bind these species to their
locale as strongly as for the previous three species because the function
is not invertible – the locale does not grip just one species.
The structure of adaptation differs distinctly between the first three
conifers and the spruces.
« previous
6 of 13 next
»
|