But not forgetting the problem of what a trait is, what T
is, what T is when O has T, Grant (1963,
p. 95) gives a well crafted factual presentation: “The webbed
feet of a duck set toward the rear of the body represent an adaptation
for swimming; the strong sharp talons of an owl are an adaptation
for clutching prey; the opposable front and rear toes of a warbler
are an adaptation for perching on branches”, wherein duck
O has webbed feet T and webbed feet T
are (is) advantageous to duck O, which is to say, is adaptive
in environment E, and, more cogently, is adapted
to environment E. But what is trait T, webbed
feet? This trait and the other two traits are, each, an adaptation.
Thus we have worked from the factual term adapted – true of
many organisms – and its sister term adaptive – showing
a tendency to become in fact true of many organisms – we have
worked from these terms to the term adaptation. One adaptation is
one entity, whereas adapted is true of many entities But to continue,
Barash (1977, pp. 57-62) gives four traits for three species of
marmots in North America. The eastern woodchuck is adapted
to a low elevation habitat and a long growing season and has
these four traits, these four adaptations: dispersal of young at
the end of the first year, sexual maturation during the second year,
annual reproduction, solitary and aggressive social system. The
Olympic marmot, by contrast, is adapted to a high elevation
habitat and a short growing season and has these four traits,
these four adaptations: dispersal of young at the third year, sexual
maturation in the fourth year, biennial reproduction, colonial and
tolerant social system. The yellow bellied marmot is intermediate
in habitat and traits. It is probable that Barash would not be interested
in the switch from ‘is’ to ‘has’, from something
is adapted to something else, x is adapted to y,
to something has an adaptation, x has y and y
is an adaptation. What interests Barash is the evolutionary change
with the changing habitats. The traits as a bundle for each species
are considered adaptive, the bundle for each species maximizing
the fitness of each species – for throughout his book on sociobiology
adaptive and maximizing fitness are regularly equated. The issue,
one can vaguely discern, is not that there is some process of evolutionary
change but that there is the accomplished fact of evolution in the
three bundles of traits being adapted to three different environments,
in the three species being adapted to three different environments.
But process is the central issue in Lewontin’s (1978) large
scale portrayal when he says “the wholesale reconstruction
of a reptile to make a bird is considered a process of major adaptation
by which birds solved the problem of flight”. This wholesale
reconstruction of a reptile includes the four traits or properties
common to all birds: hollow, lightweight bone, increased size of
sternum, change in integument to feathers for flight and insulation,
and increased forelimb. With the appearance of these traits evolution,
in personified language, made birds adapted to flight –
solved the problem of flight, metaphorically speaking.
The accomplished fact of evolution and the process of evolution
are expressed in another way (Levins and Lewontin, 1985, p. 68).
“All extant species, for a very large part of their evolutionary
histories, have neither increased nor decreased in number and range…..
At the same time, the species is evolving, changing its morphology,
physiology, and behavior. The problem is how a species can be at
all times both adapting and adapted.” A point well taken.
But now it is apparent what is wrong. The vista presented in the
last three paragraphs is so unremittingly positive. It just can’t
be right. But two more cases are the following.
Let us consider the account of Kricher and Morrison (1989, pp. 141-143).
They say that in the eastern woodchuck of the U.S.A., “the
ability to hibernate…..is an adaptation”. The grey squirrel
is pointed out because it lacks this adaptation. They want us to
believe, without a shred of evidence, that “In the past, probably
millions of years ago, woodchuck ancestors possessing the ability…..to
sleep deeply for at least part of the winter, were the ones that
survived best….and left most offspring in the overall wood-chuck
population.” They are concerned of course with the origin
of an adaptation. Here the concern, instead, is the double question:
Is the woodchuck adapted because it hibernates and is the squirrel
not adapted because it does not hibernate? It is baffling that
such an obvious contrast is not made. What they say is “an
adaptation in one species is never guaranteed to evolve in all species,
even if it would be advantageous.”
A similar line of thinking is from Seger and Stubblefield (1996,
pp. 99-102). A frequency distribution of clutch sizes for nearly
4500 clutches of great tits (Parus major) in Wytham Wood
near Oxford (England) showed that “the most productive clutch
is 12 but the commonest clutches are 8 and 9. Parents therefore
appear to lay smaller clutches, on average, than those that would
maximize their fitness.” If “maximize their fitness”
is interpreted to mean “best adapted,” then it would
seem that the commonest clutches are not the best adapted.
But the authors’ effort is to explain both statistically and
experimentally why the tits did not maximize their fitness. Their
effort is to explain away the tits’ not being best
adapted. Their thinking is confused.
This discussion has brought forward several features. Brandon provides
if-then and if-and-only-if structure; these are logical structures.
Munson provides trait; a trait is a property, a characteristic,
a universal. Both Brandon and Munson relate the trait, the property,
of being adapted to the environment. Instances of the property of
being adapted are given by Grant: the webbed feet of a duck, the
talons of an owl, the opposable toes of a warbler are instances,
examples of adaptedness (the property of being adapted). Finally
the process and the accomplished fact of being adapted are important
aspects of evolution for Barash, Lewontin, and Levins and Lewontin.
In all of these treatments only affirmation of adapted, of adaptedness
is considered, a stark fault. In what follows cases involving both
affirmation and denial of adaptedness will be presented first, and
then cases involving only the affirmation of adaptedness will be
presented second. The treatments just presented seem only to get
at the structure of adaptation and to get at it in a rather piece-meal
and unintegrated way. In what follows structure will be emphasized,
a very integrated structure. This structure will be seen to permeate
the content of adaptation.
« previous
2 of 13 next
»
|